Search This Blog

Wednesday, March 17, 2010

Deconstructing Darwin’s Theory of Literary (R)evolution

Darwin’s assertion seems solely based on his lack of reading poetry in his later years. Before the age of thirty he read the likes of Byron, Wordsworth, Shelley, Shakespeare, and many more. But as he has progressed in years, he has lost his interest in such poets, and even finds Shakespeare “intolerably dull.” In describing this “curious and lamentable loss of higher aesthetic tastes,” Darwin suggests a hierarchy in which poetry ranks higher than the novel. I find this assumption absolutely ridiculous. His claims are purely based on personal taste, and he never gives any specific reasoning for this outlook. Darwin—though accomplished, highly educated and eloquent—has no business deciding which literary form is best, or, as he calls it, “first class.” However, his suggestion could certainly change the way one approaches a text. Deeming poetry as instantly superior to the novel sets up a lofty expectation of the former, though Darwin’s prospects are terribly degrading to the poetic form.

In order to clarify Darwin’s expectations of poetry, I must first explain that of novels, the three specifics of which he details more thoroughly. And assuming that his expectations of novels are opposite or nearly so of poetry, I subsequently explain how and why my chosen case study, The Philanthropist and the Jelly-fish, fill these expectations.

He first contrasts poetry to the novel, describing the latter as “works of the imagination.” This leaves the reader to assume that poetry in itself is unimaginative. The Philanthropist and the Jelly-fish certainly fits this mold with such a supposition in mind. The poem describes an antagonist who wants to “rescue” a beached jelly-fish from certain death. The creature refuses his gesture, relaying that her demise is simply how things are. This is a response to natural selection and society’s opposition to the idea. Since the poem is based on Darwin’s own theory of evolution, it is clearly unoriginal and unimaginative.

The next must-have detail of a novel is a happy ending. Darwin does not contrast this aspect to poetry as he did previously, so the reader should not presume a poem should have a happy ending. While the reader could debate either way, The Philanthropist’s end is neither outright happy nor melancholic. It furthermore fills Darwin’s increasingly blasé expectations of poetry.

Lastly, a novel also must contain “some person whom one can thoroughly love.” This aspect is debatable in The Philanthropist. While I find the jelly-fish more agreeable—though I would not venture to say loveable—than the philanthropist, Darwin specifically writes that a “person,” not a character, must be found in a novel. The philanthropist is certainly not to be loved; he disrupts natural order. The jelly-fish seems to understand the world more so than he, therefore the reader does not even sympathize with him. Furthermore, Darwin writes that if such a person were a pretty woman, “all the better.” Though the jelly-fish is a female, she is not a person. The philanthropist is assumed to be male, but nonetheless remains genderless, therefore this detail is moot.

With these expectations of poetry explained, it seems more likely that novels, instead, are of the “higher order.” The Philanthropist and the Jelly-fish—as well as all other poetry—is unimaginative, unhappy, and sans loveable persons, at least from Darwin’s perspective. Why, then, is poetry of a higher order? Is it because Darwin assumes that it takes higher intellect to appreciate and digest poetry? I think that the answer goes back to my previous notion of taste. This “natural selection” of literary forms simply stems from a change in preference. I think what he suggests—that one form of literature is better than another—is dangerous and uninformed. To dismiss poetics as dull and unimaginative is to toss aside millennia of literary canon.

1 comment:

  1. I like your opening summation of Darwin’s aestheticism, and I can appreciate the fact the hierarchy he presents is based largely on “personal taste.” But does this necessarily make the opinion any less significant, especially given that this opinion is coming directly from his autobiography (as opposed to “Darwin’s Big Book of Literary Theory,” let’s say)? Moreover, I believe Darwin does give some reasoning for this opinion: he discusses a kind of atrophy that has taken place as he has gotten older as a result of his investigative focus. These quibbles aside, I thought you did a wonderful job of setting up your argument. The second paragraph is a beautifully concise declaration of your focus, your intentions, and your source of evidence. And I like the fact that you pushed through what you found to be “ridiculous” in Darwin’s reasoning in order to take on his argument on its own terms. This worked to your advantage, particularly with regard to your claim that Kendall’s poem is unimaginative b/c it merely presents Darwin’s theory in poetic form. (While I might not agree with this conclusion, I can understand it in the context of your post.) However, I’m not sure I follow your argument in the 4th paragraph. Shouldn’t the reader assume that poetry needs to have an *unhappy* or otherwise mal-content ending, if novels must have a happy one? And why must poetry be necessarily “blasé” in this context? Likewise for the 5th paragraph. I grew confused as to the stakes of the argument. Should poetry be likened to the novel, or contrasted to the novel? Poetry should *not* do what the novel does in order to be considered of a lower order, right (at least according to Darwin)? I thought your closing paragraph came closest to realizing the puzzle that Darwin presents us: how can we take his literary hierarchy seriously if it is itself a product of an atrophied aesthetic sense?

    ReplyDelete